Partiality in the ontology of mesology
By Rodrigo Cáceres
This article aims to articulate and develop an
immediate consequence of the mesological perspective (Uexküll’s Umweltlehre,
Watsuji’s fûdogaku, Berque’s mésologie) concerning the concept of partiality
and its correlates of inclusion and exclusion.
Introduction
The mesological perspective is a paradigm or
epistemological perspective that attempts to go beyond the dualisms that
characterize western modernity in order to recosmize our place within mediance,
i.e. the structural moment of our human existence. In other words, its
purpose is to reintegrate the unity of the dynamic coupling and concrescence
(growing together) of the individual with its surroundings. This mesological
horizon appears as a deep criticism of the notion of an ‘objective universe’ of
objects ‘in themselves’ which has taken hold of the western imaginary since the
scientific revolution. The same development towards abstraction has also taken
place from the side of the subject, mainly through Descartes’ res cogitans, the
thinking substance which is independent from its milieu. Against these developments
towards the abstraction of both subject and object, alienating them from each
other, mesology’s aim is to reconcretize or synthesize the unitary character of
mediance, where both subject and object are connected and in constant mutual
configuration.
Among mesology’s main concepts we find certain
neologisms such as ‘trajection’, ‘trajective chains’, ‘mediance’,
‘concrescence’ and ‘medial body’, concepts that are not trivial or easy to
grasp, but rather -one might say as the Buddha spoke of his dharma- they are
‘difficult to see’ (dudaso in Pali). Indeed, Berque finds himself in the
need to create these concepts in order to denote something for which there was
no word available, so it may well be that as Westerners we are not logically prepared
to think in these meso-logical terms, our way of thinking having been greatly
shaped by the Greek concepts of ‘essence’, ‘substance’, ‘nature’, ‘attributes’,
‘faculties’, etc. which tend to separate, distinguish and abstract phenomena
from their integrated character within the experiential milieu where they
concretely take place.
One of the foundational ideas of mesology is an
ontological distinction that does not exist in common language: the distinction
between environment (Umgebung) and milieu (Umwelt). This
distinction, advanced by the
German naturalist Jakob von Uexküll, denies that we are confronted to an
objective reality which we ‘recover’ or ‘represent’ inside our minds, but
rather it proposes that we are confronted to a milieu of signs (Umwelt)
that are configured or composed by our organism as the result of a contingent
history of selections of components of a common given environment or Umgebung.
In practice, this means that for all individual subjects, their surrounding
worlds are their own worlds, in the sense that it is their internal
organization which brings forth the signs with which they interact on a daily
basis.
Mesology’s notation for reality
One way of introducing the mesological
perspective is through a careful examination of its logical-mathematical
notation of reality, in which all these neologisms and concepts are
articulated:
Where r is reality, ‘S’ is the logical subject which
in this case denotes the environmental datum or Umgebung, ‘P’ denotes
the logical predicate, ‘I’ denotes a first-person perspective, ‘I’ denotes the individual
concerned and the ‘/’ denotes the existential trajector ‘as’ (en tant que).
P’ and P’’ are further trajections of the original trajection (S/P), meaning
that trajection is a recursive and unfinished process which may well continue
if the conditions for its occurrence are met.
We can note first that this formula constitutes a
multirealism, where reality is specific to the living species concerned, since each
species take certain aspects of the environmental datum and translate them into
a certain predicative field or milieu of meaningful signs which ek-sist (stand
out) to a certain first-person perspective I. If we take into consideration the
ontological distinction between Umgebung and Umwelt, then this notation of
reality has both chronological and genetic aspects, since it denotes how
reality appears historically on the basis of an already existing objective universe
or Umgebung. The Umgebung in itself as a physical or objective
domain is -before life appears on this planet- closed or concealed upon itself,
it is not disclosed nor made apparent. What life does, what living beings add
to the Umgebung is that they take it and disclose it (Heidegger’s Erschlossenheit)
by signifying it, they create an opening -just like a wound which creates a
certain depth- which is the place where the Umgebung is translated or
trajected into a certain milieu.
In a very apt metaphor for this process of trajection
or translation, Thure von Uexküll explains that “Nature may be compared to a
composer who listens to his own works played on an instrument of his own
construction. This results in a strangely reciprocal relationship between
nature, which has created man, and man, who not only in his art and science,
but also in his experiential universe, has created nature.” (von Uexküll,
1992).
In this logical principle of trajection, where reality
is neither the subject in itself (S) nor the predicate in itself (P) but
specifically the subject in terms of the predicate (S/P), we can also
see a principle of ordinality or nestedness, that complexity science renders
through the idea of an emergent dynamic, defined by Terrence Deacon as: “one in
which particular configurations of constraints on possibility result in
unprecedented properties at a higher level. Crucially, however, something that
is emergent is never cut off from that from which it came and within which it
is nested because it still depends on these more basic levels for its
properties”. (cited by Kohn, 2013, p.55) In the case of the mesological formula
for reality, one must note that the predicate (P) is both ontologically novel
and ontologically distinct from the subject, nevertheless both the subject and
the predicate are connected by the existential trajector ‘as’, thus they are
never cut off from each other.
In sum, there are actually two levels to this formula
of reality. First there is the genetic level, namely the trajection or
translation of an objective Umgebung, where it must be noted that in the
logical formula both ‘S’ and ‘/’ are not phenomenally visible, since ‘S’ in
itself is always concealed upon itself or unapparent. Moreover, the process of
trajection, where S is taken and translated into a certain predicative field is
also not perceivable, since the place or the level of sign awareness, where the
understanding of understanding begins is the place of mediance, the place of
the first-person perspective facing a field of meaningful signs. This is the
second level of this formula of reality, namely the result of this trajection,
which is mediance. The two aspects or ‘halves’ of the resulting mediance are
(1) the predicative field of signs and (2) the one or “I”, the first-person
perspective for whom these signs are apparent. In the case of humans, among the
signs apparent to a human first-person perspective we find ‘private signs’ such
as sensations of hunger, muscular tension, thirst, tastes, smell, which
characterize our ‘animal body’ as well as ‘collective signs’ such as
conventions, norms, institutions, money, etc. which characterize our ‘medial
body’.
Selection and partiality
What does it mean for an Umwelt to be partial? In his description of the relationship
between milieu and environment, Berque states that “the Umwelt is a selection that leaves aside most of the components of
the Umgebung.” Similarly, in 1954
Aldous Huxley wrote the following speaking of the function of the nervous
system:
I find myself agreeing with the eminent
Cambridge philosopher, Dr. C. D. Broad, "that we should do well to
consider the suggestion that the function of the brain and nervous system and
sense organs is in the main eliminative and not productive." The function
of the brain and nervous system is to protect us from being overwhelmed and
confused by this mass of largely useless and irrelevant knowledge, by shutting
out most of what we should otherwise perceive or remember at any moment, and
leaving only that very small and special selection which is likely to be
practically useful.
As we know, selection is a non-linear phenomenon which
simultaneously entails inclusion of the selected part and exclusion of the
non-selected part. Partiality, inclusion and exclusion are thus a direct
consequence of the fact that the living being’s self-organization must make
decisions on which elements of the Umgebung are deemed relevant and
which it will leave out of consideration. For Uexküll’s Umwelt-research this is
of great importance because it means that the Umwelts of non-human subjects
–that Uexküll understood as ‘invisible worlds’- can present signs which are
absent in the human Umwelt, such as infrared radiations, sonar perception,
magnetic field perception, etc. that as humans we are not able to know. In this
manner, the world that an organism spontaneously constitutes is a partial world
with reference to the scope of available components of the Umgebung.
At this level of the presence of qualitative signs
(such as colors, shapes, smells, sounds, magnetic fields), this issue of the
partiality of trajections/translations may not seem to raise ethical or
practical issues. However, the issue of partiality becomes problematic with the
emergence of languages, especially because of our philosophical ambitions to
achieve universality and objectivity. As I have argued elsewhere, languages emerge
as recursions of already existing human mediances (the dynamic coupling of individuals
and their milieu) that before language are for the most part constituted by
qualitative (iconic) and indexical signs (see Kohn, 2013).
Partiality also operates in language because, for a
significant part, language functions as a sophisticated way of pointing.
However, we know that pointing is basically selection, which is marked by
partiality. Whatever is pointed at is necessarily determined by that which is
not pointed at, what is left aside, out of consideration.
At a trivial level, Lakoff & Johnson (1980)
discuss partiality in the case of simple categorizations:
A categorization is a natural way of
identifying a kind of object or experience by highlighting certain properties,
downplaying others, and hiding still others. [...] To highlight certain
properties is necessarily to downplay or hide others, which is what happens
when we categorize something [...] we focus on certain properties that fit our
purposes. Focusing on one set of properties shifts our attention away from
others. For example:
I've invited a sexy blonde to our dinner
party.
I've invited a renowned cellist to our
dinner party.
I've invited a Marxist to our dinner
party.
I've invited a lesbian to our dinner
party.
Though the same person may fit all of these
descriptions, each description highlights different aspects of the person.
Describing someone who you know that has all of these properties as "a
sexy blonde" is to downplay the fact that she is a renowned cellist and a
Marxist and to hide her lesbianism. (p.163)
This kind of trivial categorization may not seem to
carry significant consequences. However, the categorizations of theoretical and
mathematical systems can be of great practical consequences. Ecolinguistic
research, for example, has provided deep analyses of how mainstream economic
theory -taught in most universities around the globe- categorizes nature and
non-human living beings (Stibbe, 2015). Within this theoretical-linguistic
construct, the main categories used to speak of the environment are ‘natural
resources’, ‘natural capital’, ‘ecosystem services’ or ‘natural stocks’, that
portray nature as a stock of resources to be exploited for economic gain. Resources
are things that humans use for their benefit, we think of resources in quantitative
terms (as in abundant, scarce, depleted) and we do not think of resources in
qualitative or even emotional terms. The resource frame necessarily downplays
the idea that nature is full of living beings with intentions, desires and
their own milieu that impacts their overall wellbeing.
This ‘nature as resource’ linguistic trajection or
translation is of common and implicit understanding among economists. However,
as a partial linguistic translation, it leaves out of consideration alternative
trajections of nature, such as ‘nature as kin’, ‘nature as source of admiration/joy/mental
health’ or ‘nature as source of life meaning’ (van der Born et al, 2018).
These alternative trajections bring forth ideas related to respect and
reciprocal relationships with the natural milieu, which are absent in the
objectifying frame of nature as mere resource.
Furthermore, when this linguistic construct is translated
or trajected into mathematical notation, nature disappears altogether. This is
the case in the general equation for the ‘production function’, which is used in
economics to study the behavior of the firm as well as the national product or
GDP. The equation is Y = F(K,L) where Y is the number of units produced (the
firm’s output), K the number of machines used (the amount of capital), and L
the number of hours worked by the firm’s employees (the amount of labor). As is
evident, in this notation there is no sign for whatever material is used to
produce the output, meaning that units are produced out of nothing! As Williams
and McNeill (2005, p.8) explain: “Raw materials used as inputs in the
production process, and any other services provided by the natural environment,
were omitted from consideration altogether. Amazingly, they still are. First
year economics students are still taught in almost all of the currently popular
textbooks that businesses manufacture their products using only labour and
machines!”. In other words, in the linguistic Umwelts of economists and
economics students, non-human beings and ecosystems are permanently excluded
from consideration other than as resources for economic growth and, when
mathematics take central stage, nature disappears altogether, and we are
confronted with an economy which is completely abstracted from the materiality
of the Earth.
Considering that mainstream economic theory and its
concepts are one of the main narratives that organize modern society (Stibbe,
2015), one must also note their attempts to universality and objectivity, which
are apparent in their usual reliance on complex mathematics as well as on metaphysical
claims such as ‘economic actors are profit-driven’, ‘economic actors are
rational’, ‘resources are scarce’ and ‘human needs are infinite’. However, the
general circumstance is that every linguistic model of a milieu is necessarily
partial, since partiality is a direct and unavoidable consequence of the
phenomenon of trajection (and in this particular case, linguistic and also
mathematical trajection).
In summary, discourses and theories in language are
necessarily always partial, in the sense that these are linguistic models that
incorporate and commit to a limited set of concepts that highlight certain
aspects of what occurs in the world in a specific way. When discourses do so,
they implicitly erase all aspects of what they do not take into consideration.
In other words, highlighting something in a discourse necessarily implies
downplaying other things. The issue is that since discourses are positive, whatever
is erased and downplayed by them remains invisible.
Another aspect that is worth mentioning concerning the
partiality of discourses and theories is that we seem to be only able to speak
about this phenomenon through conceptual metaphor, which is the most common
form of trajection in language. In other words, we cannot think about this
phenomenon with literal concepts. A simple overview of the concepts used to
speak about partiality gives us the following list: 'highlight', 'background',
'foreground', 'reveal', 'hide', 'bring to light', 'focus', 'downplay', 'shed
light upon', 'hidden side', 'visible, 'invisible', 'shift attention away from',
'apparent side', 'blurred' and 'erased'.
We have on the one hand the light/darkness metaphor,
where the 'highlighted' aspect, the one that a discourse 'brings to light' or
'sheds light upon' is the aspect that the chosen words or symbols convey. The
'obscured' or 'occult' aspects are the ones not taken into consideration by the
choice and framing of words or symbols.
We have also the vision and glasses metaphor (that function
together), where the 'visible' aspect is where the 'focus is on' and the 'invisible'
aspects are the one where our attention is not focused on, the choice of words
'shifts our attention away' from these 'unapparent' aspects. In the special
case of the glasses metaphor, the aspects not considered can be 'blurred' or 'out
of sight'.
There is then the foreground/background metaphor,
which is also an aspect of our vision, where the salient aspects are the ones
'brought to the forefront/foreground' and the aspects not considered are
'backgrounded' or 'left in the background'.
The reveal/hide metaphor is also present, where the
aspects that are 'manifest', 'revealed' or 'shown' through the choice of words
simultaneously 'hide', 'conceal' or 'cover up' the aspects that are not
considered.
Finally, in the coin metaphor, what is salient is on the
'apparent side' while simultaneously the opposite side of the coin, the 'hidden
side' or 'dark side' (a blend with the darkness metaphor) is not apparent or inaccessible
to sight.
A concluding remark
This multiplicity of ways of trajecting or translating
the phenomenon of partiality is helpful to illustrate the purpose of this
essay, which was to ‘highlight’, ‘bring to the foreground’ or ‘make manifest’
the relevance of the concept of partiality for mesology and its related
concepts of ‘inclusion’ and ‘exclusion’ or -as Arran Stibbe likes to call them-
‘salience’ and ‘erasure’ patterns (Stibbe, 2015). This also entails that the
mesological framework itself is also partial (as it is made of words). There is
one sense where this partiality implies that mesology is a work in progress
aiming for further recognition of the diversity of concrescent motions of
individuals with their surroundings.
However, more generally one needs to consider what von
Uexüll (1992) labels as the phenomenon of homomorphy: “a fundamental
principle which recurs on different levels of complexity, in different ways,
yet always in basically the same form”. Is not trajection precisely a
homomorphic phenomenon? It appears as the principle of world disclosure (S/P)
as well as the principle of linguistic trajection (S/P)/P’ and also in what is
referred to as conceptual metaphor ((S/P)/P’)/P’’ and even in mathematical
trajection ((S/P)/P’)/P’’. Why the identification of homomorphic phenomena is
of such importance for science and mesology is a question that I will not
discuss in this article. However, as it may be evident at this point, this
phenomenon of trajection or translation or metaphor is concretely functioning
more as a verb rather than as a noun. ‘To traject’, ‘to translate’ or ‘to
metaphorize’ is the action “which endlessly brings (pherei) reality
further (meta) than identity.” (Berque, 2016).
References
Berque, A. (2016). Nature, culture: Trajecting beyond
modern dualism. Inter Faculty, 7, 21-35.
Huxley, A. (1954). The Doors of Perception. New
York. Harpers.
Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we
live by. Chicago/London.
Stibbe, A. (2015). Ecolinguistics: Language, Ecology
and the Stories We Live By.
van den Born, R. J., Arts, B., Admiraal, J., Beringer,
A., Knights, P., Molinario, E., ... & Vivero-Pol, J. L. (2018). The missing
pillar: Eudemonic values in the justification of nature conservation. Journal
of Environmental Planning and Management, 61(5-6), 841-856.
von Uexküll, T. (1992). Introduction: The sign theory
of Jakob von Uexküll. Semiotica, 89(4),
279-316.
Williams, J. B., & McNeill, J. M. (2005). The
current crisis in neoclassical economics and the case for an economic analysis
based on sustainable development.
Comments
Post a Comment